Conditional_Semantics

Содержание

Слайд 2

What is a conditional?

A conditional is two propositions related by some “if...then...”

What is a conditional? A conditional is two propositions related by some
construction.
“If it is Monday, then I have class.”

Слайд 3

What is a conditional?

A conditional is two propositions related by some “if...then...”

What is a conditional? A conditional is two propositions related by some
construction.
“If it is Monday, then I have class.”
M: it is Monday
C: I have class

Слайд 4

What is a conditional?

“If it is Monday, then I have class.”
M: it

What is a conditional? “If it is Monday, then I have class.”
is Monday
C: I have class
“If’ and “then” are not part of the propositions; they are “connectives”.

Слайд 5

What is a conditional?

“If it is Monday, then I have class.”
M: it

What is a conditional? “If it is Monday, then I have class.”
is Monday
C: I have class
The proposition to the left of “then” is the antecedent, and the proposition to the right of “then” is the consequent.

Слайд 6

A big project in philosophy is to give a correct account of

A big project in philosophy is to give a correct account of
the semantics of conditionals.
(I assigned the von Fintel reading to give a sense of the project’s influence on linguistics.)
When are they true? When are they false? When (if ever) are they meaningless?

Слайд 7

today we’ll talk about

standard ways to understand the semantics of conditionals
the material

today we’ll talk about standard ways to understand the semantics of conditionals
conditional
the strict conditional
Stalnaker-Lewis semantics
and how this work connects to more general topics in cognitive science
pretense and imagination
scientific reasoning
the role of formal logic in human thought

Слайд 8

material conditional

In most introductory logic classes, you’re taught that the “material conditional”,

material conditional In most introductory logic classes, you’re taught that the “material
which I’ll indicate with “?”, is the appropriate way to think about the truth-value of a conditional in a natural language.

Слайд 9

quick note...

The “truth-value” of a proposition or sentence just means whether the

quick note... The “truth-value” of a proposition or sentence just means whether
sentence is true or false.
E.g., the truth-value of “Moscow is in Russia” is “true,” whereas the truth-value of “Barcelona is in France” is “false”.

Слайд 10

“If it is Monday, then I have class.”
M: it is Monday
H: I

“If it is Monday, then I have class.” M: it is Monday
have class
M ? C

Слайд 11

In general, a material conditional of the form “A ? B” will

In general, a material conditional of the form “A ? B” will
be false if and only if A is true and B is false.
A ? B
T T T
F T T
T F F
F T F

Слайд 12

“If it is Monday, then I have class.”
M ? B
T T T
F

“If it is Monday, then I have class.” M ? B T
T T
T F F
F T F

Слайд 13

M ? B
T T T
F T T
T F F
F T F
The

M ? B T T T F T T T F F
only time this conditional is false is if it is Monday and you don’t have class.

Слайд 14

M ? B
T T T
F T T
T F F
F T F
When

M ? B T T T F T T T F F
a conditional is true only because its antecedent is false, we’ll say the conditional is “vacuously true”.

Слайд 15

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences that

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 16

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
that seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 17

“It is not the case that, if there is a God, then

“It is not the case that, if there is a God, then
the moon is made of cheese. Hence, there is a God.”
If we interpret the conditional as a material conditional, then that inference is valid.
That’s a bit strange...

Слайд 18

proof

“It is not the case that, if there is a God, then

proof “It is not the case that, if there is a God,
the moon is made of cheese. Hence, there is a God.”
G: there is a God
C: the moon is made of cheese
~(G ? C)
G

Слайд 19

proof

~(G ? C)
G
1. ~(G ? C) assumption
2. ~(~G v C) 1,

proof ~(G ? C) G 1. ~(G ? C) assumption 2. ~(~G
implication
3. G & ~C 2, De Morgan’s
4. G 3, & elimination

Слайд 20

Or here’s another strange inference:
Imagine that a light will go on if

Or here’s another strange inference: Imagine that a light will go on
and only if you flip up both the left switch and the right switch.

Слайд 22

Then we can say “the light will go on if and only

Then we can say “the light will go on if and only
if both the left switch is up and the right switch is up”.

Слайд 23

Then we can say “the light will go on if and only

Then we can say “the light will go on if and only
if both the left switch is up and the right switch is up”.
But if we treat the conditional here as a material conditional, it follows that either if you flip up the left switch the light will go on or if you flip up the right switch the light will go on. But this conclusion is just wrong.

Слайд 24

L: Left switch is up
R: Right switch is up
O: Light is on

L: Left switch is up R: Right switch is up O: Light is on

Слайд 25

“the light will go on if and only if both the left

“the light will go on if and only if both the left
switch is up and the right switch is up”.
(L & R) ?? O
“either if you flip up the left switch the light will go on or if you flip up the right switch the light will go on”
(L ? O) v (R ? O)

Слайд 26

(L & R) ?? O
(L ? O) v (R ? O)
(L &

(L & R) ?? O (L ? O) v (R ? O)
R) ?? O Assumption
[(L & R) ? O] & [O ? (L &R)] 1, bicondit.
(L & R) ? O 2, & elimin.
~(L & R) v O 3, impl.
(~L v ~R) v O 4, De Morgan’s
~L v (~R v O) 4, paren. dist.
(~L v O) v (~R v O) 6, v intro.
(L ? O) v (R ? O) 7, impl. (x2)

Слайд 27

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences that

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 28

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences that

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 29

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences that

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 30

(a) “If Moscow is in New Zealand, then 2 + 2 =

(a) “If Moscow is in New Zealand, then 2 + 2 =
4”
(b) “If Moscow is in New Zealand, then 2 + 2 = 5”
(c) “If Moscow is in New Zealand, then Red Square is in New Zealand”
If we treat these as material conditionals, they all turn out to be vacuously true, because the antecedent in each is false.

Слайд 31

but this is a bit weird...

but this is a bit weird...

Слайд 32

(a) “If Moscow is in New Zealand, then 2 + 2 =

(a) “If Moscow is in New Zealand, then 2 + 2 =
4”
(b) “If Moscow is in New Zealand, then 2 + 2 = 5”
But how could (a) and (b) both be true?

Слайд 33

 
(c) “If Moscow is in New Zealand, then Red Square is in

(c) “If Moscow is in New Zealand, then Red Square is in
New Zealand”
Moreover, it seems (c) is true, but not just vacuously true—i.e., it is true not merely because its antecedent is false.

Слайд 34

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences that

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 35

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences that

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 36

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences that

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 37

(d) “If I were living in Paris, then I would try to

(d) “If I were living in Paris, then I would try to
learn French.”
This conditional is a counterfactual in the subjunctive mood. (More on what this means in a minute.)

Слайд 38

(d) “If I were living in Paris, then I would try to

(d) “If I were living in Paris, then I would try to
learn French.”
This creates two problems.

Слайд 39

(d) “If I were living in Paris, then I would try to

(d) “If I were living in Paris, then I would try to
learn French.”
First, can we even assign a truth-value to the antecedent? What is the truth-value of “I were living in Paris”?

Слайд 40

(d) “If I were living in Paris, then I would try to

(d) “If I were living in Paris, then I would try to
learn French.”
Second, the antecedent is false (I guess), so the whole conditional is vacuously true. But I assure you the conditional is not just vacuously true. I would try to learn French if I lived in Paris!

Слайд 41

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences that

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 42

three problems with the material conditional

the material conditional generates some inferences that

three problems with the material conditional the material conditional generates some inferences
seem wrong
the material conditional doesn’t handle conditionals with false antecedents very well
the material conditional does pretty bad with counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals

Слайд 43

the strict conditional

Before looking at the Stalnaker-Lewis approach to counterfactusl, I want

the strict conditional Before looking at the Stalnaker-Lewis approach to counterfactusl, I
to say a bit about the “strict conditional”.
This was developed by C.I. Lewis (1883-1964)

Слайд 44

C.I. Lewis

C.I. Lewis

Слайд 45

quick modal logic lesson

L means “necessarily” and M means “possibly”
(A box is

quick modal logic lesson L means “necessarily” and M means “possibly” (A
often used instead of L, and a diamond instead of M).
So L(P) means “necessarily P”, while M(P) means “possibly P”.
~L(P) means “not necessarily P” which is equivalent to M~(P) or “possibly not P”.

Слайд 46

quick modal logic lesson

What do “necessarily” and “possibly” mean?
There are different types

quick modal logic lesson What do “necessarily” and “possibly” mean? There are
of necessity/possibility. Three common types are logical/mathematical, nomological, and metaphysical.
(Further distinctions are often made, but these will suffice for our purposes.)

Слайд 47

quick modal logic lesson

“Possibly, I could jump high enough to land on

quick modal logic lesson “Possibly, I could jump high enough to land
the moon.”
If “possibly” is read as nomological, then this sentence is false. But if it is read as metaphysical, it is true.

Слайд 48

quick modal logic lesson

When people talk about “possible worlds,” they generally mean

quick modal logic lesson When people talk about “possible worlds,” they generally
worlds where the laws of physics or other arguably “contingent facts” are different.
For instance, there is a possible world at which objects move faster than the speed of light, or in which I am named “Randall,” rather than “Brian.”

Слайд 49

quick modal logic lesson
On the other hand, there is no possible world

quick modal logic lesson On the other hand, there is no possible
at which “2 + 2 = 5”, for that would be a violation of logic/math, or where an animal is both alive and not alive, for that would be a violation of metaphysics (perhaps).
Logical/mathematical and metaphysical truths are taken to hold across all possible worlds.

Слайд 50

Lewis was unhappy with the material conditional.
He said we should interpret conditionals

Lewis was unhappy with the material conditional. He said we should interpret
as claims about what is necessarily true.

Слайд 51

For Lewis, “If A, then B” is true if and only if

For Lewis, “If A, then B” is true if and only if
L(A?B) is true
We use the material conditional within the parentheses, but the L indicates “necessity”.
So in words, “If A, then B” is true if and only if “Necessarily, if A then B”.

Слайд 52

the strict conditional
One very nice feature of treating conditional statements as “strict”

the strict conditional One very nice feature of treating conditional statements as
in this sense is that the problematic inferences we saw above are invalid

Слайд 53

For instance, the following is invalid when the “if...then” part is read

For instance, the following is invalid when the “if...then” part is read
as “strict”:
~(If there is a God, then the moon is made of cheese)
There is a God
That’s (arguably) good!

Слайд 54

~(If there is a God, then the moon is made of cheese)
There

~(If there is a God, then the moon is made of cheese)
is a God
This becomes:
~[L(G?C)]
G
...which is invalid.

Слайд 55

In case you’re interested, here’s a quick illustration of why the argument’s

In case you’re interested, here’s a quick illustration of why the argument’s
invalid, using the tableaux method.
Showing why the light switch argument is invalid will take too long, so feel free to try it on your own as an exercise.

Слайд 56

~[L(G?C)] Assumption
~G negated conclusion
~[L(~G v C)] 1, implication
M~(~G v C) 3, ~L rule
M(G

~[L(G?C)] Assumption ~G negated conclusion ~[L(~G v C)] 1, implication M~(~G v
& ~C) 4, De Moran’s
G & ~C, 1 M rule
G, 1 6, & elim.
~C, 1 6, & elim.
open

Слайд 57

Unfortunately, the strict conditional has problems too.
These are called the “paradoxes” of

Unfortunately, the strict conditional has problems too. These are called the “paradoxes” of strict implication.
strict implication.

Слайд 58

paradoxes of strict implication

If B is necessarily true, then L(A ? B)

paradoxes of strict implication If B is necessarily true, then L(A ? B) will be true.
will be true.

Слайд 59

If B is necessarily true, then L(A ? B) will be true.

If B is necessarily true, then L(A ? B) will be true. Why is this weird?

Why is this weird?

Слайд 60

If B is necessarily true, then L(A ? B) will be true.

If B is necessarily true, then L(A ? B) will be true.

Why is this weird?
Well, let B be the proposition “7 is a prime number.” Most would say 7 is prime as a matter of mathematical necessity.

Слайд 61

That means...
(e) “If Moscow is in Russian, then 7 is a prime

That means... (e) “If Moscow is in Russian, then 7 is a
number.”
(f) “If Moscow is in France, then 7 is a prime number.”
are both true, if we interpret these conditionals as strict conditionals.

Слайд 62

paradoxes of strict implication

If B is necessarily true, then L(A ? B)

paradoxes of strict implication If B is necessarily true, then L(A ?
will be true.
(2) If A is necessarily false, then L(A ? B) will be true.

Слайд 63

So then these sentences turn out true:
(g) “If 2 + 2 =

So then these sentences turn out true: (g) “If 2 + 2
5, then Moscow is in Russia.”
(h) “If 2 + 2 = 5, then Moscow is in France.”
since most would say “2 + 2 = 5” is necessarily false.

Слайд 64

That’s enough of strict conditionals.
Now we’re going to move on to the

That’s enough of strict conditionals. Now we’re going to move on to
semantics for counterfactuals/subjunctives that Robert Stalnaker and David Lewis put forward.

Слайд 65

indicative vs. subjunctive
(i) “If Oswald didn’t shoot Kennedy, then someone else did.”

indicative vs. subjunctive (i) “If Oswald didn’t shoot Kennedy, then someone else
(indicative)
(j) “If Oswald hadn’t shot Kennedy, then someone else would have.” (subjunctive)

Слайд 66

One way to think about the difference is that an indicative conditional

One way to think about the difference is that an indicative conditional
attempts to describe the way the world is, whereas a subjunctive attempts to describe the way the world could have been (or would be like) if something had (or does) happen.

Слайд 67

Generally, indicatives have antecedents with verbs in the simple present or simple

Generally, indicatives have antecedents with verbs in the simple present or simple
past and no modal in the consequent. (A modal is a word like “would”, “could,” “should”).
(i) “If Oswald didn’t shoot Kennedy, then someone else did.”

Слайд 68

Generally, indicatives have antecedents with verbs in the simple present or simple

Generally, indicatives have antecedents with verbs in the simple present or simple
past and no modal in the consequent. (A modal is a word like “would”, “could,” “should”).
(i) “If Oswald didn’t shoot Kennedy, then someone else did.”

Слайд 69

In contrast, subjunctives have verbs in the past perfect or the word

In contrast, subjunctives have verbs in the past perfect or the word
“were” and a modal in the consequent. 
(j) “If Oswald hadn’t shot Kennedy, then someone else would have.”

Слайд 70

In contrast, subjunctives have verbs in the past perfect or the word

In contrast, subjunctives have verbs in the past perfect or the word
“were” and a modal in the consequent. 
(j) “If Oswald hadn’t shot Kennedy, then someone else would have.”

Слайд 71

For the purposes of this discussion, we’ll say a counterfactual is a

For the purposes of this discussion, we’ll say a counterfactual is a
subjunctive conditional with a false antecedent. E.g.,
(d) “If I were living in Paris, then I would try to learn French.”
I am not living in Paris, so the conditional is a counterfactual—i.e., it is counter to fact. It is also clearly subjunctive.

Слайд 72

Note, not all subjunctive conditionals have a false antecedent:
(k) “If Jones had

Note, not all subjunctive conditionals have a false antecedent: (k) “If Jones
taken the arsenic, he would have just exactly those symptoms which he does in fact show.” 
But for the purposes of this discussion, we’ll just be concerned with subjunctive counterfactuals, and I’ll just say “counterfactuals” from here on.

Слайд 73

David Lewis (and, before that, Robert Stalnaker) came up with a framework

David Lewis (and, before that, Robert Stalnaker) came up with a framework
for assigning a truth-value to a counterfactual that involves (a) possible worlds and (b) a “similarity relation” between possible worlds and the actual world.

Слайд 74

David Lewis (1941-2001)

David Lewis (1941-2001)

Слайд 75

Take the following counterfactual:
(l) “If kangaroos had no tails, they’d topple over.”
How

Take the following counterfactual: (l) “If kangaroos had no tails, they’d topple
do we assign a truth-value to this counterfactual?
Roughly, the Stalnaker-Lewis approach is that we go to the nearest possible world about which the antecedent is true, then see if the consequent is true at that world too. If it is, the conditional is itself true. If not, it is false.

Слайд 76

more precisely...

Bjerring’s formulation (2017, 330):
(SL) A counterfactual of the form “If P,

more precisely... Bjerring’s formulation (2017, 330): (SL) A counterfactual of the form
then Q” is true in the actual world if and only if some possible world in which P and Q are true is closer to the actual world than any possible world in which P is true and Q is false.
The “SL” refers to Stalnaker and Lewis. 

Слайд 77

So if the world at which kangaroos lack tails and topple over

So if the world at which kangaroos lack tails and topple over
is closer to the actual world than any world in which kangaroos lack tails and don’t topple over, then the conditional is true. If not, it is false.
The way Lewis was thinking about this is that you imagine some “small miracle” occurs at a world that changes the world in a surgical way from the actual world to make the antecedent true

Слайд 78

(m) “If I had struck this match, it would have lit.”
Again, this

(m) “If I had struck this match, it would have lit.” Again,
will be true precisely when the closest world to ours at which we the match is struck and it catches on fire is closer to our world than is any world at which the match is struck and it doesn’t catch on fire.

Слайд 79

antecedent strengthening
I didn’t mention this above, but yet another problem with the

antecedent strengthening I didn’t mention this above, but yet another problem with
material conditional and the strict conditional is called “antecedent strengthening.”

Слайд 80

antecedent strengthening
If “A ? B” is true, then so too is “(A

antecedent strengthening If “A ? B” is true, then so too is
& C) ? B”
and
If “L(A?B)” is true, then so too “L([A & C] ? B)”

Слайд 81

But natural languages don’t seem to work this way:
(m) “If I had

But natural languages don’t seem to work this way: (m) “If I
struck this match, it would have lit.”
(n) “If I had struck this match and the room had no oxygen, it would have lit.”
Above, (m) seems correct, whereas (n) seems false.

Слайд 82

Fortunately, with SL we can say (m) is true and (n) is

Fortunately, with SL we can say (m) is true and (n) is
false.
We’d analyze the first conditional differently than the second. With the first, we go to a world where the world is like ours but the match is struck. (So, if the room has oxygen in the actual world, it would there too.) In the second, we go to a world in which we strike the match and we remove oxygen from the room.

Слайд 83

A similar story can be told about:
(l) “If kangaroos had no tails,

A similar story can be told about: (l) “If kangaroos had no
they’d topple over.”
(o) “If kangaroos had no tails and used crutches, they’d topple over.”

Слайд 84

some issues

(1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of worlds?
(2)

some issues (1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of
What are these “worlds”?
(3) Counterfactuals with impossible antecedents

Слайд 85

some issues

(1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of worlds?
(2)

some issues (1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of
What are these “worlds”?
(3) Counterfactuals with impossible antecedents

Слайд 86

Quine’s example (about Douglas MacArthur during the Korean War):
(p) “If Caesar were

Quine’s example (about Douglas MacArthur during the Korean War): (p) “If Caesar
in command, he would use the atom bomb.”
(q) “If Caesar were in command, he would use catapults.”
(Both seem true, or at least plausible.)

Слайд 87

What world are we talking about: a world very much like ours

What world are we talking about: a world very much like ours
(e.g., 1953), but Caesar is the general?
Or a world circa 2000 years ago and Caesar is the general?
(Conversational context is relevant here.)

Слайд 88

The “uniqueness assumption” was endorsed by Stalnaker but not Lewis.
It says that,

The “uniqueness assumption” was endorsed by Stalnaker but not Lewis. It says
for each antecedent that is not impossible, there is a world that is most similar to ours at which the antecedent is true.

Слайд 89

again from Quine...

(r) “If Bizet and Verdi had been compatriots, Bizet would

again from Quine... (r) “If Bizet and Verdi had been compatriots, Bizet
have been Italian.”
(s) “If Bizet and Verdi had been compatriots, Verdi would have been French.”
If the uniqueness assumption is correct, only one of (r) and (s) is true, but it’s not clear which.

Слайд 90

some issues

(1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of worlds?
(2)

some issues (1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of
What are these “worlds”?
(3) Counterfactuals with impossible antecedents

Слайд 91

some issues

(1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of worlds?
(2)

some issues (1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of
What are these “worlds”? (We’ll skip this.)
(3) Counterfactuals with impossible antecedents

Слайд 92

some issues

(1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of worlds?
(2)

some issues (1) How do we determine the “similarity” or “nearness” of
What are these “worlds”? (We’ll skip this.)
(3) Counterfactuals with impossible antecedents

Слайд 93

squaring the circle

To “square a circle” is to use only a compass

squaring the circle To “square a circle” is to use only a
and a ruler to construct a square that has the same area as a circle
Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) believed he had squared a circle.
Apparently, it is in fact mathematically possible to do this.

Слайд 94

(t) “If Hobbes had squared the circle, he would have been a

(t) “If Hobbes had squared the circle, he would have been a
famous mathematician.
(u) “If Hobbes had (secretly) squared the circle, sick children in the mountains of South America at the time would have cared.”

Слайд 95

Because squaring the circle is mathematically impossible, and because possible worlds must

Because squaring the circle is mathematically impossible, and because possible worlds must
obey the rules of math, the above sentences are not just counterfactual, but also counterpossible—i.e., they are counterfactuals with an impossible antecedent.

Слайд 96

So how do we check to see whether these counterfactuals are true,

So how do we check to see whether these counterfactuals are true,
given the Stalnaker and Lewis approach?
We can’t go to the nearest possible world in which the antecedent is true and check to see whether the consequent is true there too—there are no such possible worlds.

Слайд 97

Lewis (and others) thought counterpossibles are all vacuously true.
A lot of people

Lewis (and others) thought counterpossibles are all vacuously true. A lot of
think this is an unsatisfying response.
Why?

Слайд 98

(t) “If Hobbes had squared the circle, he would have been a

(t) “If Hobbes had squared the circle, he would have been a
famous mathematician.
(u) “If Hobbes had (secretly) squared the circle, sick children in the mountains of South America at the time would have cared.”
To many, (t) seems true, but not vacuously so, while (u) seems false.

Слайд 99

So there are a number of people in philosophy who are trying

So there are a number of people in philosophy who are trying
to extend counterfactual semantics by incorporating “impossible worlds”—i.e., worlds about which impossible propositions or sentences are true.

Слайд 100

conditionals and pretense

conditionals and pretense

Слайд 101

A lot of reasoning that we engage in occurs when we act

A lot of reasoning that we engage in occurs when we act
“as if” something were true, then infer the consequences
This is often referred to as “pretense”, “supposition”, “make-believe”, or “imagination”
This plays an important role in everyday life (from quite early on), as well as in science

Слайд 102

“How is it possible for a child to think of a banana

“How is it possible for a child to think of a banana
as if it were a telephone, a lump of plastic as if it were alive, or an empty dish as if it contained soap? If a representational system is developing, how can its semantic relations tolerate distortion in these more or less arbitrary ways?...Why does pretending not undermine their representation system and bring it crashing down?” (Leslie 1987, 412)

Слайд 103

Effectively, Leslie is asking how counterfactual reasoning in possible in young children?

Effectively, Leslie is asking how counterfactual reasoning in possible in young children?

Слайд 104

Consider Galileo...
How would a ball roll down this inclined plane if there

Consider Galileo... How would a ball roll down this inclined plane if
were no friction?
Which object would hit the ground first were I to drop them at the same time from a large tower?

Слайд 105

Or Newton...
What would an object do were there no forces acting on

Or Newton... What would an object do were there no forces acting
the object at all?

Слайд 106

Another contemporary topic in philosophy (and cognitive science) is whether scientific reasoning

Another contemporary topic in philosophy (and cognitive science) is whether scientific reasoning
is just an outgrowth and self-conscious application and modification of the sort of counterfactual reasoning even young children can engage in
Имя файла: Conditional_Semantics.pptx
Количество просмотров: 38
Количество скачиваний: 0