Слайд 2Realist Absolutism
Thucydides: The Melian Dialogue
Realism: aim at what is feasible
“Since you
know as well as we do that right, as the world goes, is only in question between equals in power, while the strong do what they can and the weak suffer what they must”.
? No appeal to justice? Or politics refers to another form of justice where power makes right? In Plato’s Republic Thrasimacus states “justice is the advantage of the strongest” (a position that Plato refuses through the character of Socrates)
Слайд 3Realist Absolutism
Niccoló Machiavelli: The Prince
No moral basis on which to judge
the difference between legitimate and illegitimate uses of power
Authority and Power are Coequal: “Since there cannot be good laws without good arms, I will not consider laws but speak of arms”
Power defines political activity and the real point is HOW to use power
Слайд 4Realist Absolutism
Niccoló Machiavelli: The Prince
The Highest Good: A free and well
ordered state
The need for stability in a prince’s principality: at stake is its preservation
The state has no transcendent justification: it is an instrument for common good ? separation between the church and the state
The art of the state: political techniques of extreme realism Virtú: no moral connotation ? virtuous are those qualities and attitudes that contribute to the success of the prince ? a moral vice can well be a political virtue (for example, cruelty)
Prudence: considering not only the short period, but the long period as well
Слайд 5Realist Absolutism
Niccoló Machiavelli: The Prince
Commonly it is said that in Machiavelli
there is no moral basis on which to judge the difference between legitimate and illegitimate uses of power. Is it true? Perhaps there are two different kind of morality: one for common citizens (as private individuals) and another one for rulers
Flexible Disposition: varying her/his conduct from good to evil and back again “as fortune and circumstances dictate” ? The Prince should be both a Lion and a Fox because different enemies require different skills
? A very difficult talent (because of psychological predisposition to stability)
Слайд 6Realist Absolutism
Niccoló Machiavelli: The Prince
Legitimacy of law rests entirely upon the
threat of coercive force; authority is impossible for Machiavelli as a right apart from the power to enforce it.
“The answer is of course, that it would be best to be both loved and feared. But since the two rarely come together, anyone compelled to choose will find greater security in being feared than in being loved.”
Reputation
a prince may be perceived to be merciful, faithful, humane, frank, and religious, but he should only seem to have these qualities. A prince cannot truly have these qualities because at times it is necessary to act against them.
Слайд 7Realist Absolutism
STRENGHTS: Avoiding Crusades ? No wishy-washy utopianism, reality is what it
is. Refusing to fight for ideals. Creating a common ground for politics ? based on power and self-interest that all actors can recognize
WEAKNESSES: Conservativism ?No possibility of moral criticism, moral change, and moral improvement of politics. Instability ? notwithstanding the “objectivity” of the goals there is a complete flexibility of the means that leads to the impossibility of understanding what is permitted and what is forbidden
Слайд 8Idealist Absolutism
Kant: Perpetual Peace
Morality is practical: the totality of unconditional mandatory laws
? duty
“There can be no conflict of politics, as a practical doctrine of right, with ethics, as a theoretical doctrine of right.”
But Force is necessary for establishing the juridical condition (because the will of each individual is required)
Слайд 9Idealist Absolutism
Kant: Perpetual Peace
“I can easily conceive of a moral politician, i.e.,
one who so chooses political principles that they are consistent with those of morality; but I cannot conceive of a political moralist, one who forges a morality in such a way that it conforms to the statesman’s advantage.”
Слайд 10Idealist Absolutism
Kant: Perpetual Peace
It is a duty of the moral politician to
correct the defects in the constitution of a state, even it costs self-sacrifice, but slowly and carefully
Against realists: The moralizing politician that uses the excuse that human nature is not capable of the good as reason prescribes it only makes reform impossible and perpetuates the violation of law
? They have not practical science but only practices
Слайд 11Idealist Absolutism
Kant: Perpetual Peace
Fundamental question: In problems of practical reason, must we
begin from its material principles, i.e., the end as the object of choice? Or should we begin from the formal principles of pure reason, i.e., from the principle which is concerned solely with freedom in outer relations and which reads “So act that you can will that your maxim could become a universal law regardless of the end”?
Certainly the second option!
Political moralist: technical problem ? prudence but results for peace are uncertain
Moral politician: ethical problem ? wisdom will lead slowly to peace
Слайд 12Idealist Absolutism
Kant: Perpetual Peace
“Seek ye first the kingdom of pure practical reason
and its righteousness, and your end (the blessing of perpetual peace) will necessarily follow”
First right means than good ends will follow, or in other words, only through the right means it will be possible to achieve good ends
“All politics must bend its knee before the right. But by this it can hope slowly to reach the stage where it will shine with an immortal glory.”
Слайд 13Idealist Absolutism
STRENGHTS: Belief in a better world ? idealism pushes toward action
in order to improve conditions. Moral clarity and “objectivity” ? because ordinary values and principles are a duty also for politics.
WEAKNESSES: Rigidity ? once rights are in force they can not be taken away even if this means the ruin of the entire community. Moral Crusades ? notwithstanding the Kantian reformist attitude this ideal type can lead to a position that refuses any compromise and tries to impose its view on others
Слайд 14Realist Pragmatism
Weber: Politics as Vocation
Definition of the state in terms of means:
the state is a human community that (successfully) claims the monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force within a given territory
? Politics: striving to share power or striving to influence the distribution of power either among states or among groups within a state
Слайд 15Realist Pragmatism
Weber: Politics as Vocation
Three forms of legitimacy:
Traditional (patriarch)
Charismatic (individual leadership)
Legal (servant
of the state)
? The modern problem of party-machines and plebiscitarian democracy
Слайд 16Realist Pragmatism
Weber: Politics as Vocation
Three pre-eminent qualities of a politician:
Passion: devotion to
a cause but not romanticism
Responsibility: guiding star
Sense of Proportion: distance toward one’s self (politics is made with the head)
Power instinct is important but it becomes dangerous if it moves from being an objective to a self-intoxication
Слайд 17Realist Pragmatism
Weber: Politics as Vocation
Two deadly sins in the field of politics:
Lack
of objectivity
Irresponsibility
Ethics in the field of politics needs to take into consideration that the means of politics is violence
Absolute ethics does not ask for the consequences
Слайд 18Realist Pragmatism
Weber: Politics as Vocation
Ethic of Ultimate Ends
VS
Ethic of Responsibility
“There is
an abysmal contrast between conduct that follows the maxim of an ethic of ultimate ends – that is, in religious terms, ‘The Christian does rightly and leaves the results with the Lord’ – and conduct that follows the maxim of an ethic of responsibility, in which case one has to give an account of the foreseeable results of one’s action”
If an action of good intent leads to bad results:
EUE: the world, stupidity, or God is responsible for the evil
ER: takes into account the deficiencies of people and the results are ascribed to one’s actions
Слайд 19Realist Pragmatism
Weber: Politics as Vocation
“In numerous instances the attainment of ‘good’ ends
is bound to the fact that one must be willing to pay the price of using morally dubious means or at least dangerous ones – and facing the possibility or even the probability of evil ramifications.”
Слайд 20Realist Pragmatism
Weber: Politics as Vocation
“The ethic of ultimate ends apparently must go
to pieces on the problem of the justification of means by ends. As a matter of fact, logically it has only the possibility of rejecting all action that employs morally dangerous means – in theory! In the world of realities, as a rule, we encounter the ever renewed experience that the adherent of an ethic of ultimate ends suddenly turns into a chiliastic prophet. Those, for example, who have just preached ‘love against violence’ now call for the use of force for the last violent deed…”
Слайд 21Realist Pragmatism
Weber: Politics as Vocation
“Also the early Christians knew full well the
world is governed by demons and that he who lets himself in for politics, that is, for power and force as means, contracts with diabolical powers and for his action it is not true that good can only follow from good and evil only from evil, but that often the opposite is true. Anyone who fails to see this is, indeed, a political infant.”
Various life-spheres each governed by its own laws
Protestantism legitimated the state (especially the authoritarian state) as a divine institution and hence violence as a means
The necessity of endangering one’s own soul
Слайд 22Realist Pragmatism
STRENGHTS: Moving into reality ? although the individual involved in politics
should be passionate he needs to be aware of the limits of reality. Stressing responsibility ? entering into politics does not mean to be free to do whatever one wants, it implies to sacrifice one’s morality
WEAKNESSES: Aristocratic view ? politics at its best is a game for charismatic leaders. The darkness of one’s soul ? It is difficult, if not impossible, to ascertain whether the sacrifice of the soul for the welfare of the community is real or just a mask.
Слайд 23Narrow Pragmatism
Marta Nussbaum, The Costs of Tragedy
Nussbaum structures a contraposition between:
the obvious
question – what ought we to do?
and the tragic question – is there a morally acceptable choice?
The tragic question answers to the first level of desirability problem: holding ordinary times’ standard it is possible to understand that the tragic question registers the equal undesirability of any solution.
Слайд 24Narrow Pragmatism
Marta Nussbaum, The Costs of Tragedy
“[The obvious question] may be difficult
to answer. It may also be difficult to identify the best method for arriving at the answer. […] What is not difficult, however, is to see that it is a question that has to be answered, since some action must be taken, and even inaction
Advantages:
first, it clarifies the nature of the ethical alternatives;
second, it remembers and reinforces the commitment toward some values that we are obliged to overcome in the obvious question;
third, it considers the possibility of reparation for the unethical conduct;
fourth, it forces to ask if it is possible to bypass the tragic question with a better social planning
Слайд 25Narrow Pragmatism
Walzer, The Problem of Dirty Hands
Politician claims to act in our
name
Politicians are ruling over people
Politicians can use violence or the threat of violence
Question: how can we (as politicians) get our hands dirty by doing what we ought to do?
Ex. 1) The honest politicians that needs to get his hands dirty in order to get elected and doing good
Ex. 2) The ticking bomb scenario
The idea of feeling guilty
Слайд 26Narrow Pragmatism
Walzer, The Problem of Dirty Hands
Dirty Hands: The necessity of feeling
guilty while doing what ought to be done
Against Utilitarianism:
Utilitarian calculus will fully justify the action because it maximizes the outcome, but it will delete the sense of guilt: his hands will be clean because he did what he ought to do
Rules are not really prohibitions of wrongful actions, but simply moral guidelines: no necessity of feeling guilty
Using the sense of guilty as a variable inside the calculus: but if it is useful why should he feel guilty once he made the calculation?
Слайд 27Narrow Pragmatism
Walzer, The Problem of Dirty Hands
The example of a correct application
of dirty hands can be Camus’ The Just Assassins: terrorist in XIX century Russia. “The heroes are innocent criminals, just assassins, because, having killed, they are prepared to die – and will die. Only their execution, by the same despotic authorities they are attacking, will complete the action in which they are engaged: dying, they need make no excuses”
A comparison with Civil Disobedience (an illegal action, different from criminality because: publicity, appeal to common reason, accepting the punishment)
Problem is how to punish the politician
Слайд 28Narrow Pragmatism
Combining Nussbaum and Walzer:
Recognizing the unavoidability of wrongness as a matter
of tragic question in order to keep ordinary morality evaluation alive
But then doing what is necessary to do as a matter of obvious question, dirtying one’s hands
In other words, a separation between the justification and the action
Слайд 29Narrow Pragmatism
The problem is that in this way we lack a criterion
for deciding what to do. If what we are doing is morally wrong, then can we do whatever we want? Or is there a particular decision procedure with a secondary form of justification? The Obvious question is a Not-So-Obvious-Question
Ignatieff proposed the idea of Lesser Evil (instead of maximizing good, we should try to minimize evil), but this does not solve the problem, it simply reformulates the not-so-obvious-question as a matter of peculiar cost-benefit analysis